By Selwyn Duke
Do not judge lest you be judged . . . . It's a phrase so frequently misused nowadays. It's often uttered in an attempt to immunize oneself against value judgments about one's behavior. After all, few people brook criticism very well, and many of us fear the re-emergence of a dominant moral code that might cast a pall over the libertine lifestyle modern man holds so dear. So the aforementioned misused Bible quotation and other fashionable mantras are trotted out and used as a firewall against the bearers of bad news. You may hear, "Don't impose your values on me!" or "Who's to say what right and wrong are" or "That may be right for you, but that doesn't mean it's right for others." We've all heard these refrains in one form or another, and many of us have used them ourselves. It seems as if civilization's moral compass is adrift in a Bermuda triangle of moral confusion — there no longer is a consensus among people about what's right or wrong. So we feel we have the latitude to deflect inconvenient value judgments with these convenient little clichés; we pay homage to the notion that what's right is negotiable. But do we really believe this? And what, if anything, is wrong with the prevailing conception of right and wrong in our society? To answer these questions one has to examine the nature of right and wrong.
I mentioned that oft-uttered phrase "Who's to say
what right and wrong are?" And that
really is the first question that must be asked: Who is to say what right and wrong are? Well, there are only two possibilities: Either
man does or something outside man does. T he idea that man determines right and
wrong is known as "moral relativism"; this means that morals are
relative to the time, place and people. The idea that right and wrong are
determined by something outside of man is known as "Absolute Truth."
How society answers this question has serious implications, because embracing
one belief or the other will determine which path mankind takes. They are diverging roads that lead to places
that are as different as Heaven and Hell.
It's important to realize that the question being asked here
is nothing less than whether or not morality actually exists — whether it's a
fantasy or a reality. For instance, Mars
exists, but not because people believe it does but because it actually does —
it is a physical truth. Twenty thousand
years ago people weren't aware of its existence, but that had no bearing on the
fact that it did exist. And, even if
every soul on this planet were in the grip of the delusion that it wasn't there
and insisted to the ends of the Earth he was right, that orb would still be
present. Conversely, a fictional planet
in a movie only exists in the imagination, and even if everyone insisted that
it was real it wouldn't make it so — its existence isn't a physical truth. But, of course, physical truths can eventually
be verified scientifically given enough research. But what about right and wrong? Does man's beliefs about it have equally
little bearing on its nature and existence? Is there moral truth just as there is physical
truth?
Needless to say, moral relativism answers these questions
with a resounding "no." Once
again, it states that morality is determined by man; what is rarely recognized,
though, is that if this is so then there is no right and wrong, objectively
speaking. Think about it: If 90 percent
of humanity said it preferred chocolate ice cream over vanilla, it wouldn't
mean that chocolate was "right" and vanilla "wrong." Nor
would it mean that chocolate was better in any objective sense — it would
simply mean that people happened to like
chocolate better. It's illogical to say
otherwise. But, would it be any more
logical to say that murder was wrong for no other reason than the fact that 90
percent of all people preferred that others not kill in a way that we call
unjust? Of course not. But if the idea that murder is wrong is simply
a function of man's collective preference, it then falls into the exact same
realm as the collective preference for a type of ice cream: the realm of taste.
Now, let's think about what this implies. First, it means that Hilter's heinous acts
weren't wrong; it means that rape, murder and all the acts and ideas that you
find to be most abhorrent aren't wrong; it means that killing your most
cherished loved one wouldn't be wrong. All
we could then honestly say about these things is that we don't happen to like
them, as right and wrong simply wouldn't be in the equation. After all, if "right and wrong" is
synonymous with "opinion," then the former is an unnecessary phrase
that just serves to obscure the issue and confuse the mind.
Now, even if someone claims that relativism rules the day, he
still no doubt will instinctively act as if certain things are very wrong. He may become very passionate about certain
issues and various things may offend him. But why? Why the contradiction? It's very simple:While his intellect is
telling him that there is no Truth, his feelings betray him. He feels
as if certain things are very wrong. This
brings me to the second implication of relativism: If morals are relative, then
all his "feelings" about right and wrong are just that — feelings —
they have no basis in reality. And this
means that he's out of touch with reality, which some would call being crazy. But if we're crazy because we wrongly (in the
estimation of the relativists) feel and act as if there is right and wrong,
then who are the sane ones? Well, they
would be those who recognize reality and behave accordingly — that reality
being that right and wrong don't exist. And
who would these people be? They would be
the true sociopaths: People who have no consciences whatsoever and who
consequently have no negative emotional reactions at all to what we would
consider to be evil. Some of these
people might be Saddam Hussein, Adolf Hitler, Ted Bundy and John Wayne Gacy.
The last implication of relativism that I'd like to mention
concerns the matter of debating about morality. And bear in mind that the majority of debates and
virtually all of the most rancorous ones do have to do with it; why, even a
debate about welfare policy concerns morality. After all, regardless of your opinion on the
subject, the fact is that if determining which policy is best is truly an
imperative, it's only because it's "right" to help the poor. But, consider this: If there's no Truth, there
is no point in engaging me in a sincere debate (one that is not for sheer
entertainment, ego satisfaction or simply helping you get what you want) about
right and wrong. This is because if
there is no Truth, there is no right or wrong, in which case you couldn't be
any more wrong or right than I could be. And then, since the only purpose of a sincere
debate is to determine what the correct stance (the Truth) on the issue at hand
is, there wouldn't be any point engaging me in it. Therefore, when you engage someone in sincere
debate, you are tacitly acknowledging that Truth exists.
These are the unarguable implications of moral relativism. To accept moral relativism is to entertain the
idea that nothing — not genocide nor cannibalism nor child-molestation nor the
darkest transgression conjured up by the most deviant mind — is any worse than
swatting a fly. It's to entertain the
notion that you are in fact crazy and those bereft of a conscience are the sane
ones. It's to entertain the idea that
every debate you engage in is a pointless exercise, which, if not pursued
solely for pleasure, only serves to confirm your dislocation from reality. Do you really believe these things? Because you'll have to if you want to be true
to moral relativism. There is no middle
ground — either Truth exists or it doesn't. If it doesn't, then relativism does carry the
day. Sure, you could choose to live in a
fantasy world wherein you pretended as if certain things were meaningful and
important in order to make existence more tolerable, as relativism gives you
that luxury. It dictates that living a
lie isn't wrong, you see. But make no
mistake about it, it would be a fantasy world.
And what are the implications of the existence of Absolute
Truth? Well, for one thing it means that
we aren't the authors of right and wrong — something above us is. It means that we are all subject to the same
standard of morality, one that won't bend to suit our whims, justify our sins
or ease our consciences. This frightens
many people because it threatens their rationalizations. And here I think of a well-known and quite
effete social commentator I saw on television who actually said "The idea
of Absolute Truth scares me." I'm
sure it does. But there is something
such people should find even scarier: a civilization that denies Truth's
existence. This is because if people
conclude en masse that there is no absolute, immutable and universal standard
of right and wrong, then you'll have no luck in convincing them they should be
civilized. For you'll only be able to
refer to your opinions and those of your philosophical soul mates when trying
to convince them to act rightly. All you
can say is, "Do this because it is what I would have you do; do it because
it's my will." They will then
simply say that they are people just like you, with opinions, desires and a
will of their own; they'll ask you why yours should take precedence. And what could you say? It would be fruitless. You might as well try to convince them that
there's some overriding reason why they should prefer your flavor of ice cream.
When society has degenerated to this state, its members can
justify anything they might want to do. If
it pleases them emotionally to kill, rape or steal, many will see no reason not
to. After all, who is to say it's wrong?
You shouldn't impose your values on
others, you know, and my truth might be different than yours . . . .
Every time we let these justifications pass our lips, we are
contributing to an atmosphere in which every person is his own author of right
and wrong. And, if we persist in this,
it will eventually make us the publishers of some of the darker chapters in the
annals of human history.
© 2010 Selwyn Duke — All Rights Reserved
This is an outstanding argument against moral relativism!
Posted by: Dominic Wohltman | August 24, 2016 at 09:25 PM
If all that you said holds true, then it follows that there must exist one absolutely true religion. And only one. The idea of absolute truth was lost because society abandoned the one absolutely true religion. How to reverse society's disdain for truth? Teach them to love the only true religion.
Posted by: Thomas Naegele | August 26, 2016 at 09:30 PM
I'm not so sure Thomas. What if no single religion is in possession of all truth? Or what if some religions possess certain truths, while others possess other truths? I agree with the notion of there being an objective and absolute truth that exists independent of men or men's opinions. And personally, I believe that Christianity offers the world the most complete set of absolute truths. It is troubling, however, to see so many different interpretations of the Holy Scriptures, and so many different beliefs even among the Christian sects.
What may be required is a fresh revelation from the one Being who is in possession of all truth. That would settle things. Maybe for a while, anyway.
Posted by: Kirk H | September 03, 2016 at 12:38 AM